Notes � animal behaviour revision citations

Greg Detre

Monday, 20 May, 2002

Social learning (teaching/imitation)

Recent critical reviews of the known cases of imitation in primates challenge all such claims and offer more parsimonious explanations based on social facilitation and stimulus enhancement (Whiten 1989). Similarly, teaching has been restricted to humans, although in one case a sign-language-trained chimpanzee, attempted to mould and influence the signing performance of a younger companion (Fouts et al. 1982)

Chimpanzee mothers may influence the development of nut cracking in three ways (excluding the very wide-spread nut sharing) (Boesch & Boesch 1984):

1.       stimulating

2.       facilitating nut-cracking

3.       active teaching

They observed two cases in which the mother, noticing the infants� difficulties, made a clear demonstration of how to solve them, e.g. Ricci�s 5-year old daughter, Nina

All functions attributed to human tutoring by Wood et al. (1976) seem to be performed by chimpanzee mothers here. Recruitment, direction maintenance and marking critical features are apparent in the stimulations, frustration control and scaffolding in the facilitations as well as in teaching alongside with demonstration.

Common ravens have a reputation for being intelligent. They are ecologically highly adaptable, are both neophobic and neophilic (Heinrich, 1988, 1995), long-term monogamous and territorial for most of their life, but also flock.

pine-cone stripping of black rats (Zohar & Terkel 1996) or the opening of milk bottles by great tits (Sherry & Galef 1990).

Stimulus enhancement

observation of a model�s activity makes the location or object of the model�s behaviour attractive for an observer (Thrope 1963, Galef 1988, Campell & Heyes in press). Heyes (1994) defined stimulus enhancement as one-stimulus learning, involving no association between the location or object and the reward.

Observational conditioning

Defined as a kind of classical conditioning, where the observer associates the location or object with the reward obtained by the model (Cook et al. 1985, Heyes 1994).

Both stimulus enhancement + observational conditioning can increase the probability of the observer learning an operant task.

Motor imitation

Motor imitation is defined as learning the operant task directly through the observation of the model�s behaviour (Heyes 1994, Zentall 1996). It is usually considered the cognitively most demanding category of social learning (for the observer), since it requires the translation of a visual input into a matching motor output which may involve more complex central processing than other mechanisms of social learning (Whiten & Byrne 1988, Heyes 1988).

Although a number of studieshave focused on the imitative ability of different primate species (e.g. Byrne 1995, Whiten et al 1996, Bugnyar & Huber 1997), a few nonprimate mammals, such as rats (Heyes et al 1992, Heyes 1996), and several bird species, e.g. budgerigars (Galef et al 1986), grey parrots (Moore 1992), pigeons (Zentall et al 1996) and Japanese quails (Akins & Zentall 1996), the conclusiveness of the evidence for imitation learning is still debated (Visalberghi & Fragaszy 1990, Byrne & Tomasello 1995, Heyes 1998, Gardner & Heyes in press). Studies on �lower� mechanisms of social learning, e.g. enhancement or observational condition, are rare.

Palameta & Lefebvre�s (1985) study of pigeons showed that observers were only sufficiently motivated to peck through a paper lid on dish when they saw a conspecific doing it, but not when they only saw the model either pecking or eating. This suggests that the pairing of a demonstrator�s response with a secondary reinforcer is very important.

Dawkins (1993), �Through our eyes only�:

Brunton and Macdonald used radiocollars to follow rats� movements on a farm where a major extermination attempt had failed to kill more than a third of the rat population

Galef paired rats in cages, showed the observer rat to avoid/choose foods that harm/feed demonstrator rats

Caro & Hauser do not think that teaching depends on complex intentionality or attribution of mental states, although intentionality plays some role in some forms of teaching

Thorndike (1898) provided a clear definition of imitation �learning to act from seeing it done�

but I don't think that�s clear enough � it doesn't take into account behaviour that�s somehow/implicitly influenced by watching someone else as opposed to an actual attempt to reproduce it???

Tayler and Saayman (1973) report the amusing story of a captive dolphin that, after repeatedly seeing a diver cleaning a viewing window, started cleaning the window with a seagull feather while emitting sounds almost identical to those of the diver�s air-demand valve and relaeasing a stream of bubbles from its blowhole

Hayes and Hayes (1952) report training a chimpanzee to obey the command �Do this� with an attempt to copy their own behaviour. They further report that their chimpanzee appropriated a lipstick, stood on the washbasin and applied the cosmetic to her mouth.

Byrne and Byrne (1991) report that mountain gorillas learn to process herbs in specialised fashions that vary across local populations

Kawai (1965) reported that potato-washing of a juvenile female, Imo, was soon adopted by most of the younger members of the group. There has been much subsequent questioning of this finding. Green (1975) noticed that only the members of the group that showed this behaviour were given potatoes by provisioner so that the behaviour could easily have been caused by simple reinforcement. Galef (1990) looked at the time scale over which the novel behaviour spread and found that the mean and median times for the acquisition of this trait were two years, surely imitation would allow behaviour to spread almost instantly through a population, as is suggested by the experimental studies of imitation.

Fisher and Hinde (1949) proposed that the annoying habit that tits developed in urban areas of opening milk bottles and drinking the first few centimetres could have been developed independently in a few tits and then been acquired by the population through observational learning.The theory was based on the observation that the behaviour seemed to start in one area and then spread outwards. Sherry & Galef (1990) have shown experimentally with black-capped chickadees that na� birds that had observed a model opening cream tubs are more likely than non-observers to adopt the behaviour themselves.

Spence (1937) was the first to propose stimulus enhancement

Dawson and Foss (1965) developed the �two-action test� that distinguishes imitation from local enhancement.The paradigm is that a na� animal will watch a model obtaining food by one of two action patterns

Fritz and Kotrschal (1999) used the two-action test to investigate social learning in ravens

Gallese & Goldman (1998) report finding neurons in monkeys that respond to a particular behaviour whether it is performed by the subject or by a monkey that the subject is watching

Manning & Dawkins (1998) � cultural transmission

song dialects passed down generations � very reliably for the short song of the black-capped chickadees (Ficken and Popp, 1995)

opening of milk bottle tops by blue tits (Hinde & Fisher 1952)

but Sherry & Galef (1984) showed that such cultural transmission could occur without imitation (i.e. without one bird actually seeing another open a bottle)

European blackbirds give alarm calls to a stuffed owl or even a plastic bucket if they had heard their parents� alarm calls while looking at them (Curio et al. 1978)

cultural evolution can affect genetic evolution, e.g. the Japanese macaques who learnt to wash their food ventured towards the sea, then started swimming and eating sweaweed etc. (Bonner, 1980 or Wilson, 1985)

Cognitive

Menzel & Erber (1978) honey-bees learn rapidly and retain very well the effects of even a single association between a colour and food reward

some animals store food from a rich food source for later, either in a single larder, or scattered in caches around their territory (Sherry 1985), e.g. the marsh tit or Clark�s nutcracker

Tolman (1932) rats build up a mental picture/cognitive map of the whole maze during exploration + learning

K�r (1927) on chimpanzees � showed that they can overcome increasing hurdles to get their bananas

Pepperberg (1990, 1991) on the African grey parrot (Alex) � can count to six, identify the quality (i.e. shape, colour) common to a group of diverse objects

Harlow (1949) � a monkey is faced with a pair of objects, one with a reward, one without � it learns which is which � then a new pair of objects, same rules � after 100 or so tests, the monkey simply lifts up one, and then selects that one ever after if it had the reward

Warren (1965) all vertebrates except fish have have the ability to form learning sets

Humphrey (1976) the complexities of social life, especially in the primates, provided one of the most important selective forces behind the emergence of thinking ability

Povinelli et al. (1992): experiment that suggested that chimpanzees have the ability to understand the outcome of their own actions, the way that these affect another individual, and also to put themselves effectively into that individual�s place. two chimps on either side of the apparatus � two food trays inside � the experimenter shows the informant chimp which handle to pull (I think) to get the food, who has to then gesture the information to the operator chimp. the operator chimp has to appreciate the significance of the informant�s gestures and, after the swap, take on this gestural role � it does so spontaneously, and using its own gestures which are not necessarily the same as those it had seen used before by its partner

Premack & Woodruff (1978): chimp was shown a video of a human being using objects well-known to the chimp, and in need of something (e.g. shivering with cold with an unlit stove, or trying to open a locked door). then the chimp was shown photographs of objects, one of which offered a solution (e.g. the burning wick of the stove, a key)

Pfungst (1965) Clever Hans

elephants: large brains, complex social life, longevity comparable with ours. perhaps significant infrasonic (8-10Hz) communication between them (Poole et al. 1988), Payne (1999)

Gould (1981) described intelligence as the ability to deal flexibly or creatively with problems

Gardner (1983) placed emphasis on symbolic processing as the hallmark of intelligence

Byrne (1995) gives the following definition: �the term intelligence should be restricted to that quality of flexibility that allows individuals to find their own solutions to problems; genetical adaptations, by contrast, are fixed and inflexible, however well tuned to their environments they are.�

Tool use has been discovered in other animals, sea otters use stones to open shellfish, chimpanzees use twigs to fish for insects, even adapting the shape of the twigs to make them more suitable, and wooden hammers to open nuts. These behaviours are not innate and, certainly in the case of chimpanzees are learnt by young from their mothers (McGrew, 1998)

Theory of mind

Heyes (1998) �theory of mind� = �an animal with a theory of mind believes that mental states play a causal role in generating behavior and infers the presence of mental states in others by observing their appearance and behavior under various circumstances�

i.e. �mental state attribution� (Cheney & Seyfarth 1990)

Dennett�s levels of �intentionality� (see Byrne, 1991)

zero-order intentionality of the eyed hawk-moth (recounted in Byrne 1991)

learnt, non-intentional but intentional-seeming behaviour can be divided into two types: a) associative learning, or b) as a product of inferences about observable features of the situation rather than mental states (Heyes, 1993)

Gilgil the female baboon�s grooming + meat-snatching (observation by Strum, cited as personal communication in Jolly 1985)

Hauser (2000) relates his observation of Tristan�s alarm call when being chased by Borgia

Whiten and Byrne�s (1988) 253 accumulated reports along similar lines are persuasive

Gallup (1969) mirror test: �knowledge of mental states in others presupposes knowledge of mental states in oneself and, therefore, that knowledge of self paves the way for an inferential knowledge of others�

apparently, this ability to recognise their own images in mirrors has been replicated over 20 times, with a variety of species, but mainly primates

Reiss & Marino (2001) two bottle-nosed dolphins, Presley and Tab could recognise themselves in the mirror

Povinelli (1998) they may simply have extended their motor self-concept, rather than have developed a psychological one � the evidence that chimpanzees are unable to imagine someone else�s perspective is quite strong

Cheney & Seyfarth (1980, 1990) found that vervet monkeys give alarm calls on seeing a predator even if other monkeys have already seen it

de Waal chimpanzees do not appear to trust the reassurance gestures of their former opponents unless such gestures are accompanied by a mutual gaze

Premack & Woodruff (1978) �Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?�

Wimmer & Perner (1983) devised the Sally-Anne false belief test for young children

Baron-Cohen et. al. (1985) autistic children fail to make an important cognitive leap that usually takes place around age four when children learn that others may have different beliefs about the world from their own

Bloom and German (2000) false belief test places high cognitive and linguistic demands on infants and animals, far beyond the possession of a theory of mind

Donald Davidson (1975) from Dennett (1995) �claimed that only creatures with the concepts of truth and falsehood can properly be said to have beliefs, and since these are meta-linguistic concepts � only language-using animals such as human beings can have beliefs�

Dennett (1995) employs a �maximally permissive understanding of the term� �belief� � �even amoebas - like thermostats - have beliefs�� cf also McCarthy (1979)

Halperin (1995) Siamese fighting fish as candidates for having beliefs (intentional interpretation), but neural-net-like model of their control systems that seems to lack any components with the features beliefs are often supposed to have

Byrne (1995) great apes definitely do have a theory of mind, but that the case for monkeys seems especially weak, and little better for dolphins or other non-primates

Language

Bright (1984) �Animal language�

Payne (1995) recordings of humpbacks in Bermuda

Tyack (1986) used playbacks of the social calls, which brought the singing whales to home straight in on the loudspeaker at 12km/hour � considered that the song may be used as a spacing mechanism for courting males

Norris (1991) studied the social structure and behaviour of groups of Hawaiian spinner dolphins

Bastian (1964) conducted a famous experiment with two dolphins, able to hear but not see each other

John Lilly probed dolphins� propensity to mimic by getting them to follow a count up to ten and recognisably say simple English words

Fisher & Ford (1983) sounds of killer whale pods are very stable, comprised of about 12 distinct, stereotyped calls, that they use to communicate when spread over a couple of miles

Hockett (1960, 1966) devised a set of 13 linguistic universals:

semanticity and arbitrariness, productivity, interchangeability, specialization, displacement, cultural transmission, duality of patterning; auditory-vocal channel; broadcast transmission and directional reception; discreteness; rapid fading):

Gardner & Gardner (1989) Washoe

by the age of five, she had mastered 133 signs. She had been spontaneously combining signs after learning only 8 or 10

Terrace (1979) Nim Chimpsky, less successful, rewarded with approval rather than food, used symbols in the absence of their referents, but not novel generation

Fouts et al. (1989) no sign language was used by humans in Loulis� presence, yet he was still able to learn 51 signs just from the other chimpanzees

Kanzi (Savage-Rumbaugh 1991)

Pepperberg (1991) Alex the grey parrot

our ethical anthropocentricism may be regarded in the same light that slavery is now (Cavalieri & Singer 1993)

Communication, deceit

Wilson (1975) �Communication occurs when one individual�s actions provide a signal that changes the behaviour of another individual�

Shannon (1948)

Wiley (1983) �noise� in terms of attenuation, extraneous environmental distractions and any deficiencies in the signaller�s encoding or receiver�s decoding equipment

rufous-sided towhees (Richards 1981) �alerting signal� an initial burst of loud sound of unvarying pitch preceding the more complicated warbling of the song which follows

Dawkins & Krebs (1978) case for �manipulation�, where every communication balances the selfish attempt of the signaller to increase its fitness, against the selfish attempt of the receiver to increase its fitness

Hamilton (1964) presented this as a 2x2 matrix, ranging from mutuality (where both signaller and receiver benefit), deceit, eavesdropping and �spite� (where both suffer from the communication).

Rohwer�s (1977) experiment with black patches on Harris� sparrows exemplifies how the costs to the signaller of being probed and exposed may be high

young male elephant seals (Le Boeuf 1974) who have evolved to look like females in order to sneak past the bull elephant into his harem suffer costs from probing by the female receivers, who emit loud screams during copulation

red deer (Clutton-Brock & Albon 1979)

emphasis placed by ethologists on handicapping signals (Zahavi 1975) has since been undermined (Maynard Smith 1976)

Blumberg & Alberts (1992) caution distinguishing functions and effects (e.g. humans babies with respiratory distress syndrome that paediatricians listen for)

vs similar laryngeal braking in the Norway rats (Blumberg & Alberts 1990), and the mother�s acute auditory sensitivity in this range, they assume that the ultrasonic squeaks produced are some sort of �distress call�

Manning & Dawkins � stimuli + communication

different modalities:

birds may have very conspicuous ultra-violet markers (Burkhardt 1989), which they use as a private channel of communication

or snakes see infrared radiation from warmblooded prey (Newman & Hartline 1982)

Von Frisch (1967) showed that bees can use the pattern of polarisation of light to locate the sun�s position even when it�s obscured (with a small dorsal region of the retina with a row of analysers each maximally sensitive to a different e-vector direction)

smell, e.g. mice � a pregnant female mouse will abort her entire litter if she smells a strange male mouse near (because they eat newly born mice that aren't theirs) (the �Bruce effect�)

odour cues associated with the MHC affect behavioural (i.e. who a mouse nests with, chooses as a mate (Lenington, 1994)) as well as cellular recognition

may be the case with human females rating the smell of t-shirts � reported that pleasanterfrom men most different from them in the MHC (Wedekind et al. 1995), and that the disimilar ones reminded them most of their former mates

deaf turkey hens kill most of their chicks because they never receive the auditory sign-stimulus for parental behaviour (Schledit et al. 1960)

Tinbergen (1951) pointed to false positives as one of the most conspicuous characteristics of innate behaviour

e.g. male sticklebacks (that normally respond aggressively to the red colouration of rival male sticklebacks) also display to a red mail van visible through the windows of the aquarium

Lettvin (1959) six different sorts of frog ganglion cells

Arak and Enquist (1993) supernormal stimuli emerge spontaneously in computational models that rely on a few key sign stimuli

males sporting super-normal plumage may be favoured, leading to an evolutionary exaggeration of both male plumage and female preference� (Fisher, 1958)

Davies and Brooke (1989) showed that spotted flycatchers and reed buntings (which currently don't get parasitised) were very good discriminators of model cuckoo eggs, whereas meadow pipits were much less discriminating but don't get parasitised because their diet/nest site aren't appropriate for cuckoos

sensory systems are adapted to pick out �information-rich� parts of the environment (Barlow 1972) � postulated grandmother cells at the top of the hierarchy

separate pathways in mammals for movement + form (Zeki 1993)

e.g. neurons in the temporal lobe of rhesus monkeys that fire up to 20 times more rapidly when looking at a face (monkey or human) than for lines, gratings or non-face complex objects (Baylis et al. 1985)

we would say that the scent trail is a signal used for communication by the ants, but although the snake undoubtedly obtains information from it, we wouldn't want to say that the ants communicated with it (Burkhardt, 1970)

Altmann (1962): social communication = a �process by which the behaviour of an individual affects the behaviour of others�

Hinde + Rowell (1962): classified as visual signals only those that were likely to have evolved for this purpose

van Rhijn (1980) saw that younger jays tend to give way to more powerful older members, even with only a minimal �signal� (e.g. displacing younger ones from food just by looking at them) once the rank order had been established (although they would escalate into a recognisable threat display if the minimal signals were ineffective)

same with dogs + coyotes, bowing + wagging their tails (Darwin 1872, �The expression of the emotions in man and animals�)

chimpanzees touch and kiss each other�s hands in gestures of reconciliation (de Waal 1996)

Payne & McVay (1971) humpback whales may communicate over distances of hundreds+ miles

hyenas smear grass stems with past from their sub-caudal scent glands and deposit faeces at latrines, either all round, or just in strategic places if the borders are too big (Mills & Gorman 1987)

the extent to which signaller and receiver�s interests coincide is an important factor in how conspicuous the signals are (Dawkins & Krebs 1978), e.g.:

red deer (see below)

gazelles stotting (see below)

on the other hand, cooperating animals communicate with �conspiratorial whispers� (Krebs & Dawkins 1984)

conflict between signaller + receiver leads to selection pressure for signals to be �honest�, i.e. proof against cheating/bluffing (Zahavi 1987)

red deer (Clutton-Brock & Albon 1979)

gazelles (Fitzgibbon & Fanshawe 1988)

skylarks sing when being chased by merlins (Cresswell 1994)

young canaries� begging signal (wide open mouth) � their mouths� red lining is due to the suffusion of blood � parents feed the reddest mouths, as their means of deciding whose need is greatest (Kilner & Johnstone 1997) � after being fed, the blood is diverted to the gut, and the mouth gets paler

Ristau (1991) argues that plovers giving a broken wing display monitor the behaviour of the predator (e.g. fox) and adjust their behaviour according to whether the fox is following them or still heading for the nest

Munn (1986) describes two species of insect-eating birds that appeared to deceive their flockmates by falsely giving alarm calls and so gaining unrestricted access to food

Byrne & Whiten (1988) consider possibly deliberate baboon behaviour � although anecdotal, they argue there are enough examples to support the idea that some animals can be deliberately dishonest

Gould (1975) summarised + proved von Frisch�s (1967) conclusions

Cheyney & Seyfarth (1980, 1990) vervet monkeys (Africa),elegant + group-living

evolutionarily stable strategy (Maynard Smith 1982) � an ESS is a strategy that, if adopted by most members of the population, cannot be bettered by any other strategy (one new mutant strain)

domestic fowl (Schjederup-Ebbe 1935) linear hierarchy � lots of fighting to begin, but once established, subordinates almost always defer to a more dominant bird

the black bibs of male house sparrows � if a weak animal has a dominant badge, it gets constantly challenged by other dominant individuals (Moller 1987), and so pays a cost for its deception (which may be enough to keep the number of cheats pretty small)

Kin recognition/selection

R. Dawkins (1976) �The Selfish Gene�, green beard, memes

Dennett (1987) �The intentional stance�

Hamilton, W. D. (1964) �The genetic evolution of social behavior�

Axelrod & Hamilton�s (1981, 1984) theoretical work on the Prisoners� Dilemma

Wilkinson�s (1984) observations of regurgitation of blood by vampire bats

lionesses are far more effective hunting zebras together than alone (Caraco & Wolf 1975)

Jarvis (1994) considers two species of mole-rat

Holmes and Sherman (1982) showed that sibling recognition in Belding�s ground squirrels is heavily skewed by those they have been reared with

Yamazaki et al. (1976) mice preferred to mate with mice that differed at the MHC even when genetic background was controlled

Brown & Eklund (1994) MHC similarity outweighs the effect of the entire remaining genetic background

Belding�s ground squirrels (Holmes & Sherman 1982)

in the sweat bee, the willingness of the guard bee to let in other bees was directly correlated with their relatedness (Greenberg 1979)

Emlen (1990) reports that 45% of helping in the white-fronted bee-eater is directed to rearing full siblings, and that on average r=0.33 between helpers and nestlings

Grafen (1990) argues convincingly that in the majority of cases where kin recognition has been reported, the ability to do so has arisen as a result of some other function and so should not be termed kin recognition as such; indeed, in many of these cases he argues that the demonstrated ability to recognise kin is not selectively advantageous or even of any functional value at all.

Manning et al. (1992) - house mice - communal nests, nurse other�s pups indiscriminately; kinship theory - should form nests with relatives to minimise exploitation and increase inclusive fitness? Females prefer communal nesting partners that share allelic forms of mhc genes. Grafen�s (1992) criticisms

Blaustein suggests four possible mechanisms for recognition:

based on spatial distance

based on familiarity, prior association

based on phenotype matching

based on action of recognition alleles

Social

Allee et al. (1938) showed that water fleas cannot survive in alkaline water, but the respired CO2 of a large group could be sufficient to bring down the alkalinity

adult meerkats (socially living mongooses) take turns �baby-sitting� the nest-hold (watchign for predators from a high look-out point) while the others are away foraging (McDonald 1986)

group living mongoose, satiated adult adopts raised sentry position while the other group members forage for food, watchman�s song (Benekoff, 1997)

naked mole rats (Jarvis 1981) average relatedness 0.81 (monogamy plus in-breeding), wouldn't survive on their own or in pairs, tips the cost-benefit-relatedness analysis in favour of self-sacrificing, life-long worker sterility

Damaraland mole rat (Jarvis et al. 1994)

Florida scrub jays (Woolfendon & Fitzpatrick 1984): helpers gain by having more siblings, they tend to take over their parents� territory in the future (at the cost of deferring reproduction for a year or so, but nest sites are highly in demand)

snapping shrimp (Duffy 1996) lives in sponges on tropical reefs, in colonies of <300, but only one reproductive female (the �queen�). like termites (Wilson, 1971) and mole rats, the shrimps are diploid and the �workers� are full sibs. food seems to be abundant, so the workers are mainly for defence, because sponge �homes� are sought by various (larger) species on the crowded reef

multiple mating is not in the interests of males, e.g. male dragonflies� penises have elaborate hooks to try and scoop out the sperm from other mates stored by the female when mating (Waage 1979)

huge male elephant seals dominate stretches of beach and fight over the females � in some seasons, 4% of the males are responsible for 85% of the matings (Le Boeuf & Peterson 1969)

no complete agreement on why primate organisation is so diverse (Ridley 1986)

Rowell (1974) critised the way the notion of dominance hierarchies has been used: dominance may be more important in captivity than in the wild

but pretty linear hierachy in Barbary macaques (Deag 1977)

Kummer (1969) transplanted a few yellow baboon females into a hamadryas troop, which were quickly herded into harems � they didn't respond to the male�s stare, and fled, but were chased back into the harem, and learnt their lesson � thus, at least some of the variation in social organisation between primate species is cultural rather than genetic

Zahavi (1974, 1995) showed that Arabian babblers would pretend to feed the young in the nest and if there were no other adults near-bye would then eat the food themselves, suggesting that there must be benefits in being thought of as a good helper or the animals

Bateson (1982, 1988), himself, found that quail prefer the company of first cousins to brothers or third cousins and that birds mated to first cousins breed rather earlier.

In mice the MHC genes have been shown to alter behaviour in three contexts. It has been shown that mice prefer to mate with individuals differing from themselves at this group of loci (Yamazaki et al., 1976). Females are more likely to nest communally with females that are the same at the MHC (kin selection), a pregnant female will often abort a litter or engage a �pregnancy lock� if she smells a strange male (Lenington, 1994). This is clear evidence of individual recognition and a corresponding active change in behaviour. More information will be discovered about the genetic influences of kin recognition as genetic understanding and technology improves.

Porter et al. (1978) showed that spiny mice prefer to associate with siblings rather than non-siblings but that the discrimination was based on the mice an individual had been housed with and was therefore altered by familiarity

Grafen (1990) defines recognition as �recognition by genetic similarity detection.�

Wilkinson (1984) investigated food sharing amongst vampire bats

Grinnel, Packer and Pusey (1995) suggest that there are three possible routes through which cooperation may develop:

1.       kin selection (Hamilton 1964) is the theory that the inclusive fitness effects of cooperation can outweigh the temptation to defect because the payoff for cooperation exceeds that of defection.

2.       reciprocity (Trivers, 1971; Axelrod and Hamilton, 1981) a theory that involves looking at repeated interactions with reference to previous behaviour, reciprocate cooperation and exclude defection

3.       mutualism (Maynard Smith, 1983; Lima, 1989) when it is considered that there is no temptation to defect because the payoff from cooperating is always higher no matter what the behaviour of the opponent. The first two theories involve conditional cooperation, mutualism is unconditional because the individual will always cooperate.

Nowak & Sigmund (1993) win-stay, lose-shift (Pavlov)

One of the most commonly cited examples of cooperation amongst animals is the lion. They rear cubs, defend territories and hunt together. Legge (1996) describes them as �an emblem of cooperation.�

Computational models/simulations, robots

Levy (1992)

R. Dawkins (1986) �The Blind Watchmaker�

Paley (1802), �Natural theology�, Paley�s watch metaphor

Reynolds (1986) boids (separation, alignment, cohesion)

Mitchell (1998), common GA methods: �populations of chromosomes; selection according to fitness; crossover to produce new offspring; and random mutation of new offspring�, GA = biologically-inspired �parallel population-based search [for solutions] with stochastic selection of many invidividuals, stochastic crossover and mutation�

Holland (1975) early GAs

Hillis (1990) coevolution in sorting GAs

Yaeger (1992) even recounts how he hadn�t even realised that he�d forgotten to switch mutation on for the first weeks of his PolyWorld investigation

Anastasoff (1999) evolving, dynamic level of mutation

Rasmussen (1991), 'Aspects of Information, Life Reality, and Physics'.

1.) A universal computer is indeed universal and can emulate any process (Turing)

2.)��� The essence of life is a process (von Neumann)

3.)��� There exist criteria by which we are able to distinguish living from non-living things

Accepting (1), (2) and (3) implies the possibility of life in a computer

Conway�s (1970) game of life

Evolutionary psychology

Pinker (1997)

Consciousness

Griffin (1992) �Animal minds�

Nagel:

(1974) �What is it like to be a bat?�

(1979) �Panpsychism�

Dennett (1991) �Consciousness explained�

M. S. Dawkins (1993), �Through our eyes only�

Jaynes (1976) �Origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral mind�

�auto-pilot� (Baars 1988, Weiskrantz 1995 (the �British Weather Conversation Syndrome�))

Greenfield (2001)

Wittgenstein (1953), �Philosophical investigations�

Tinbergen, four problems

Tinbergen (1963) �On aims and methods of Ethology�) � causation, survival value, ontogeny and evolution

based on Huxley�s (1942) tri-partite distinction

�Behavior is all observable or otherwise measurable muscular and secretory responses (or lack thereof) and related phenomena in response to changes in an animal's internal or external environment.� (Grier and Burk, 1992)

M. S. Dawkins (1989) �The future of ethology: How many legs are we standing on?�

Hailman�s (1977) partitioning individual/population and cause/origin

Mayr (1963) for example stresses the dichotomy between functional and evolutionary biology, using the terms �proximate cause� and �how� questions in relation to functional biology and �ultimate cause� and �why� questions in relation to evolutionary biology

Dewsbury (1992) attacks the proximate-ultimate distinction

 

Spandrels and the Panglossian paradigm

Gould & Lewontin (1979), �The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme�

�The design is so elaborate, harmonious, and purposeful that we are tempted to view it as the starting point of any analysis, as the cause in some sense of the surrounding architecture. But this would invert the proper path of analysis. The system begins with an architectural constraint: the necessary four spandrels and their tapering triangular form�

Dr. Pangloss: "Things cannot be other than they are... Everything is made for the best purpose. Our noses were made to carry spectacles, so we have spectacles. Legs were clearly intended for breeches, and we wear them."

Harner (1977) proposed that Aztec human sacrifice arose as a solution to chronic shortage of meat (limbs of victims were often consumed, but only by people of high status)

the eskimo face, once depicted as "cold engineered" (Coon, et al., 1950), becomes an adaptation to generate and withstand large masticatory forces (Shea, 1977).�

this nonadaptive hypothesis (about T-rex�s short forelimbs) can be tested by conventional allometric methods (Gould, 1974, in general; Lande, 1978, on limb reduction)